|
Tony Smith has written
an interesting review(1) of my book
that invites a controversial reply. Which is more than can be said of the
first, uncomprehending German review. I shall proceed by quoting point
for point from Smith's review and responding. Although inelegant, this
method has the merit of covering the issues raised.
-
Referring to my early
1984 book, Smith remarks affirmatively that
"Eldred and his co-authors
insisted on a systematic reading in which capitalism is the object of investigation
from the beginning, with transitions from one level of theoretical abstraction
to another justified logically by the immanent contradictions arising in
the former." This dovetails nicely with Smith's own 1990 book The Logic
of Marx's Capital: Replies to Hegelian Criticisms that defends a systematic
dialectical reading of Marx's main work. He erroneously claims that
"these authors
[Eldred et al.] insisted that money is the only form in which value ever
appears", thus flying in the face of our attempt to unfold, through a systematic
dialectic of concepts, a structured manifold of value-forms from
the commodity and money form through to the revenue-form of value and on
to the social forms of competitive society and state. Although Smith says
that my 1984 book "has greatly influenced a number of Marxian theorists
concerned with the methodological framework of Marx's theory and his relationship
to Hegelian dialectics", to my knowledge, not even the revenue-form
of value, present already in Marx's drafts for Capital and forming
the linch-pin in our attempt at a transition to competitive society, has
played any role in Anglophone Marxist debates on a dialectical theory of
capitalist society. Only Reuten & Williams (1988, 1989) have a stunted
reference to "income sources". This implies that the insights of value-form
analysis for developing a social ontology of capitalist society have yet
to be taken on board.
-
"'Social ontology' in
Eldred's understanding of the term combines a phenomenological description
of the fundamental structures of human existence with a normative account
of the institutional framework best enabling the actualization of those
structures." Smith misconceives phenomenology as some kind of
"description", which is so feeble that it has to be supplemented by an energy drink of norms. Hence he
underestimates — or rather, entirely overlooks — the phenomenological power of learning to see
what you already see. Here it is important also to elucidate the subtitle of my
book. Why is there a reference to "recasting" and "whoness"? Why do I hazard
to introduce a strange neologism into political and social philosophy? If
I am doing social ontology, why does Smith assert that I am providing a
"normative account"? If that were the case, Hegel's Philosophy of Right
would be just as open to this charge. The latter is a dialectical unfolding
of the concept of freedom, just as a grounded concept of freedom
is crucial to all I have to say about society and state. "Recasting" refers
to the need for radically going back to the roots where the first beginning
of social and political philosophy was cast by Plato and Aristotle.
Only in the confrontation with these key co-casters of Western thought
can any fluidity come into today's socio-political thinking on the deepest
level that would enable a recasting in another historical light.
Western metaphysics' figures of thought, such as essence, substance, existence,
subject, power, energy, etc., that are present today in all the everyday
ways of thinking and all sciences, including advanced physics, sociology,
economics, Marxist theory, etc., proceed from the original Greek productionist
paradigm. This is an important lesson to be learned from Heidegger's momentous,
ground-loosening re-readings of Plato and Aristotle. Heidegger's own focus
of attention, however, requires twisting. What of Platonic and Aristotelean
ethics that remains a separate branch alongside metaphysics, i.e.
ontology? Ethics is concerned with good ways of living together, and thus
with habitual, customary practices. Today's ethical discourse has long
since degenerated into talk of what ought to be, of what is morally justified,
of normative principles. The ontology implicitly underlying Plato's
and Aristotle's ethics is productionist, e.g. in Aristotle's account of
rhetoric in the Nicomachean Ethics. Neither Plato nor Aristotle
ever worked out explicitly a social ontology. This remains
a desideratum to the present day. A productionist ontology, however, cannot
adequately come to terms with phenomena of sociation in society, because
it proceeds from whatness (essence) in the third person. Hence the indispensable
need for radically recasting Aristotelean ethics as a social ontology
of esteem based on a concept of whoness. Hence my neologism. Smith
does not mention this crucial concept of my work at all.
-
"The central category
in the social ontology Eldred defends is 'singularity'. This Heideggerian
notion..." My concept of singularity is just as much Hegelian, and both
Heideggerian and Hegelian lines of thought are interwoven in my book. Indeed,
singularity as one of the three moments of the Hegelian concept, alongside
particularity and universality, plays a leading role in showing up the
antinomies of competitive social living and the democratic state as a ceaseless
power play. Contra Hegel's Philosophy of Right, I argue that
the moment of singularity in the ontological concept of freedom can never
'close together' in a conclusion, as Hegel attempts to show. Both Heideggerian
and Hegelian singularity, insofar as they concern human freedom, proceed
from the "nothingness" (Heidegger) or "total indeterminacy" (Hegel) of
individual free Dasein or individual free will, respectively. In any case,
singularity is not the "central category" of my social ontology, but rather
the intimately intermeshed cluster of concepts: esteem-value-power that
is first won through grappling with Aristotle's ethics. In the first place
it is human individuals in interplay with one another who, in exercising
their individual powers, strive for esteem, value and socio-political power.
-
"Hayek, a far more consistent
liberal, emerges as the true intellectual hero of this book,...". This
judgement derives from neglecting the grounding of socio-ontological concepts
of whoness, esteem, value and social power, especially in the all-decisive
Chapter 5 of my book. Although I have learned from Hayek as an insightful
liberal thinker, I also criticize him incisively in Chap. 5 vi) b) for
an ontologically inadequate understanding of market interchange. But more
than this: I criticize liberalism in toto for an inadequate socio-ontological
foundation. It hangs in the air. Liberalism, being largely Anglophone in
origin and sentiment, suffers throughout from empiricism (truth as factual
correctness) and analytic philosophy (modern scientific method) to the
extent that it cannot understand at all the issues of developing ontological
concepts within an openness to time-space where the beingness of beings
takes shape.
-
"'Value' for Marx is
a social property of things, and the private act of embodying labor in
a product cannot create such a social property by itself." The problem
with Marx's account of value is that it is ambivalent. Like Marxists
today, he wanted to have it both ways: both a dialectical unfolding
of value-forms and a determination of value magnitude by time under some
qualification ("socially necessary"). This ambiguity results in endless
quarrels among Marxists themselves, instead of their consistently developing
a value-form analytic (i.e. socio-ontological), systematic dialectical
theory based on phenomenological conceptual transitions. Thus, for example,
Smith continues to speak of commodity value being "created" — an erroneous productionist
conception that must be seen for what it is. Marxists these days also still
want to have it both ways by acknowledging there is such a thing as a systematic
dialectic while in the next breath providing also historical-dialectical
accounts of capitalist development, which are nothing other than souped-up,
more or less refined narratives that are pale and vague shadows
of a genuine dialectical unfolding, which must be conceptual. Indeed, all
so-called historical-dialectical accounts, which at best are historical
illustrations
of interrelations among dialectical categories, must presuppose the phenomenon
of time that is thoughtlessly and simply taken for granted
without ever attaining even a ghostly semblance of a thought-through concept.
Here, again, a return to Aristotle is indispensable for uprooting and recasting
the ontological conception of time that is all-pervasive in every discourse
today. One must first admit that time is presupposed as the universal washing-
line on which narrative events can be hung, which is fine for story-tellers
but not for thinkers. Even the modern mathematical sciences presuppose
the washing-line of a real, linear, one-dimensional time on which to hang their equations
(cf. my Digital Cast of Being for
details).
-
"Eldred 'ontologizes'
the liberal view that individuals freely determine and pursue their own
ends in capitalism." One must first learn what it means to 'ontologize'.
What I add to this liberal view, in a deeper grounding, is that individual
freedom is wedded intrinsically with an ongoing power struggle. This is
perhaps regrettable for those seeking Messianic Utopias.
-
"Eldred's Heideggerian
concept of capital..." A major bone I have to pick with Heidegger
and Heideggerians is precisely that his thinking has no concept whatever of capital, nor
any interest whatsoever in grasping the ontology of capitalism. When I sublate
the Marxian critical system of capitalist economy into an historical constellation
of being I call the gainful game (which is alien and even anathema to Heideggerian
thinking), this does not imply uncritical affirmation but, on the contrary,
a critical bringing-to-the-mind's-eye of how things are. I do not
by any means dispute Marx's insistence on "the ceaseless augmentation of
value". Nor, however, do I ignore the same Marx's insight in the Grundrisse
that "exchange of exchange-values is also the productive, real basis of
all equality and freedom". In their competitive struggle
with capitalist firms, workers are by no means powerless, nor are they
invariably the losers, nor are they lacking in freedom or in formal equality
with their capitalist and other adversaries. Their exposure, along with
all
the other players, including the capitalists themselves, to the necessity
of capital accumulation as an essential rule of the gainful game, goes
intimately hand in hand with the enjoyments of the freedoms of civil society
and also with the rare possibility of singular freedom for those brave
enough to risk it.
-
"Eldred's Heideggerian
concept of capital illicitly abstracts from the most essential matter:
'capital' is a totalizing drive that imposes its end on society with coercive
force." The striving for capitalist gain, for profit and accumulated profits
that can be reinvested, is just one striving among the four elementary
gainful strivings of the four classes of income-source owners: workers,
functioning capitalists, finance capitalists, landowners already present
in the drafts to Capital. Everybody is out for gain, and this is
the major motivating drive not only in economic life, but also in democratic
politics (the gain in esteem, social standing, wealth, public honour, political
power, etc.). The gainful game is totalizing, not capital accumulation.
Therefore the Marxist theory of state, according to which the state is
nothing but an agency for furthering the accumulation interests of the
capitalist class, is perniciously abstract in the Hegelian sense
of being fixated on a single conceptual determination. And what is this
'society' on which capital putatively imposes its drive? 'Society' invariably
turns out to be some kind of fictitious 'we', as in e.g. 'we, the working
class'. The appeal to "human ends [that] necessarily tend to be sacrificed
whenever that furthers this [capital] augmentation" is likewise
an appeal to a fictitious 'we'. Why? Firstly, because the appeal to "human
ends" is a consequence of modern subjectivist metaphysics that is
worthy of radical questioning. Secondly, because the gainful game and the
striving to have more infects all humans, not just the capitalists. The
underdog status per se does not justify the proclamation that the
workers are hard done by. Nor are workers' strivings per se better
than anybody elses'. Nor does any envisaged socialism overcome the gainful
game — it just shifts its rules of play in the direction of the ceaseless
political
power play, democratic or otherwise.
-
"Marxian theories of
the structural limits of the capitalist state are ignored rather than refuted."
True. My book is concerned with socio-ontological issues of value, esteem,
social power, freedom, and not with functionalist explanations of the capitalist
state, Marxian or otherwise. Social science, Marxian or otherwise, is the
demise of thinking that goes to the roots, which means posing questions
of being in its manifoldness, thus opening the possibility of a recasting
of historical time-space. This does not amount to the vision of overcoming,
i.e. getting rid of capitalism, but of getting over it.
-
"Finally, Eldred confidently
proclaims that any attempt to overcome capitalism will inevitably degenerate
into totalitarianism. Contributors to the 'models of socialism' debate
in this journal and elsewhere vehemently dispute this assertion." The term
"models" already signifies a kind of thinking that is at home with the
(questionable, untrue) scientific method of the modern age. Such a way
of thinking precludes from the outset ontological questioning, i.e. digging
deeper. Indeed, Smith pays no attention whatsoever to my sustained attempt
to think through the ontology of social powers. On this hinges my
verdict that socialism must end in totalitarianism in the sense of the
annihilation of the free individual as such who is historically possible
only in concert with the — admittedly two-edged and dangerous — reified
social power of money. The way of thinking precipitated already in
social-democratic states and societies with their social-totalitarian creep
painfully crops individual freedom in a trade-off of freedom for social
security. Freedom becomes a synonym for democracy, and democracy stands
for the era of Here Comes Everybody (James Joyce) in which singularity
is devalued. Political democracy, along with its mass media mediation,
also often shows the face of mass egoism, for everybody always wants to
have more. 'Wanting to have more' is a theme introduced in the early chapters
of my book.
-
"Twenty years have passed
since Fukuyama first made that [end of history] assertion, years in which
capitalism has brought about increasing inequality, economic insecurity,
environmental destruction, wars, massive global imbalances, recurrent financial
crises, and now, perhaps, global depression." This sob-story narrative
could be matched with other, more uplifting accounts. On the level of narrative,
nothing at all can be decided, since other plausible narrative twists and
turns are always possible. Political struggle is always a matter of pitting
one narrative against the other. More importantly, the critical diagnosis
of the past two decades shifts according to the basic socio-ontological
perspective adopted, which is prior to any explanatory narrative
and presupposed by it. Hence the decisive ground for debate shifts back
to philosophy. Genuine philosophical strife is a clash of ontological concepts.
Smith justifiably raises "[t]he question whether there might be a superior
way to institutionalize singularity and mutual recognition", that is, superior
to a liberal society. Putting aside the consideration that "to institutionalize singularity and
mutual recognition" is presumably a contradictio in adjecto, if this question is to
be approached in a way that
promises any faint hope at all of resolution or even a gain in clarity,
the social ontology of esteem, value and the social power play, through
considering who human beings are and could be in historical
time-space, must be foundational and crucial to such a debate. Instead of calling for an
institutionalization, the freedom of singularity hangs rather on the ethos of an
atmosphere, i.e. on the attunement of an age.
-
"But the position Eldred
himself defends suffers from a fatal flaw: he presents a social ontology
lacking an adequate concept of capital." In my book I only sketch a concept
of capital (e.g. Chap. 9 vi) ) whilst referring back to my earlier, unrepudiated
1984 book, which contains a full dialectical unfolding of a concept of
capital up to the democratic state. In later work (Eldred 2000, 2010),
the concept of capital is aufgehoben (waived, saved and raised) in the
concept of the constellation of being I term the gainful game mediated by the
movement of reified value. What
I called the subject of competition in 1984 has become today the player
in the gainful game. Is Marxism capable of learning something new? Qua Marxism,
of course not. It would have to (learn to) question its own socio-ontological presuppositions,
to which it remains blind.
There are many other
issues, but this is enough for the time being.
|